July 6, 2009 marks the 65th anniversary of Swedish diplomat Raoul
Wallenberg's humanitarian mission to Budapest and January 17, 2010
the 65th anniversary of his disappearance in the Soviet Union. After
protecting the lives of thousands of Jews in Nazi occupied Hungary,
Wallenberg was arrested by Soviet forces in early 1945. He was never
heard from again and the full circumstances of his fate have never
been determined.
Historians and journalists view events through a variety of prisms, so
it is important to understand the philosophical underpinnings of such
evaluations. The Raoul Wallenberg case is no exception. Over the last
few years there have been several attempts at a deeper interpretation
of both his mission and his person. For example, historians have
asked to what degree exactly Raoul Wallenberg (an honorary citizen of
the U.S., Canada and Israel) - should be considered a hero of the
Holocaust - how many lives did he really save? Is he recognized purely
for his deeds or because he disappeared? - , from which followed
questions about the relevance of his still unsolved fate.
What many people may not realize is that such considerations directly
reflect the ascendancy of the so-called 'post-modern' influence in
current political thought. Very broadly put, postmodern philosophy
questions our ability to be truly objective, no matter how hard we
try. Post-Modernism, in its various guises like logical positivism and
deconstruction, is everywhere. It is an idea system that grew out of
World War I, as an attempt to explain the horrors humanity wrought
upon itself, in an attempt to make sense of a world that had ceased to
make sense long ago. It has led to a revolution in art, music,
philosophy and the social sciences. As any influential movement does,
it has inspired fervent criticism and counter movements, while also
spurring intriguing cross pollination with more traditional strains of
philosophy.
Somewhat ironically - as will become apparent in a second -
Post-Modernism owes a great debt to science, in particular to physics
and Werner Heisenberg's 'Uncertainty Principle.' Heisenberg postulated
that both actions and perceptions influence reality as we know it.
Perception, then, is relative, as is everything else we like to call
'fact'. From that follows the question whether there is or ever can be
any certainty or "objective truth" - a very important issue,
especially for historians.
Philosophers like Ludwig Wittgenstein and later Jacques Derrida
focused on the ambiguity of language in the evaluation of historic
events, in particular the use and meaning of specific terms like
"victims" and "heroes", which led to new ways of thinking and posing
questions about "morality" and "moral choices". As a result, scholars
began to examine the past more cautiously, asked more poignant
questions, considering issues from different angles and perspectives.
Take the case of Auschwitz, the most notorious group of Nazi
concentration camps in Poland from 1940-45. Altogether, about three
million people died there at the hands of ruthless Nazi criminals.
Guilt and innocence can be easily apportioned in this situation, with
clear distinctions between perpetrators and victims. But in the years
since World War II, more subtle questions have emerged on the issue of
"guilt": Are those who refused to bomb the railroad tracks leading to
Auschwitz as responsible as those who operated the gas chambers? Do
all Germans carry collective guilt for Hitler's crimes? The victims,
too, did not escape this critical examination. Why was there so little
spirited resistance? Did some Jewish leaders focus more on creating a
new homeland than on rescuing their own from certain death? Why has
comparatively little attention been given to other victims of Hitler's
mania, such as the millions of civilians who died at the Eastern
Front?
Such detailed analysis is often welcome and helpful. However, some
critics of postmodernism, like the Austrian philosopher Karl Popper,
saw important problems with "relativism" being taken to its logical
conclusion. Since Post-modernists argue that everything we examine is
a priori tainted by subjectivity, it becomes difficult, if not
impossible, to discuss people or events objectively, never mind to
judge them appropriately. Excessive nuance can, therefore, lead to
inaction and paralysis. Taken to extremes, it will lead to the failure
of drawing any distinction between good and evil. Proponents of
Sweden's neutrality policy faced this dilemma in very practical terms,
during and after World War II.
Finally, if there are no universal truths, logically there cannot be
any universal values, shared by all humanity. Just ask the U.N. Human
Rights Council how difficult it is to gain consensus on that subject.
Popper's main objection to post-modern thought was precisely this
issue, namely that it often failed to provide workable application to
problems in the real world. Specifically, Popper felt that human
suffering could not be addressed through semantics or elaborate
thought constructs alone, but that it required concrete actions. His
recommended antidote for totalitarianism was openness - the free flow
of ideas. His book "The Open Society" became the most influential
philosophical textbook of the Cold War era, and heavily influenced
leading politicians of the day. Former Czech President Vaclav Havel
and other Eastern European leaders have paid tribute to Popper's
philosophy as a catalyst in their fight against communism and the
basis for restructuring emerging societies in Eastern Europe. The
international financier George Soros, Popper's one-time student, has
heavily funded Eastern European research and aid projects. His "Open
Society Archives" in Hungary not only reflect his deep admiration for
his teacher, but his conviction that Popper's concepts retain their
applicability in the post-communist era.
How does all of this relate to Raoul Wallenberg? If in modern analysis
victims can become "relative", so do presumptive heroes. That is often
a good thing -- the world knows the dangers of blind adulation and
simplistic, often aggressive moral certainty only too well. But such
analysis can be taken to absurdity, as Swedish historian Attila Lajos
did a few years ago. He claimed that in 1944, Hungarian Jews had not
been the helpless victims historians have made them out to be. Since -
in Lajos' view - they had not been helpless, (there were, after all,
dozens of active resistance groups in Hungary) they did not require a
heroic rescue. Ergo, Raoul Wallenberg cannot be considered a heroic
figure. His fate, too, becomes far less significant in such an
approach.
Aside from the fact that Lajos' reasoning is deeply flawed -- one look
at Hungary's deportation statistics for 1944 would put any debate to
rest - the problem is that in the final analysis, certain things are
not relative. They simply are. Just like you cannot be a little
pregnant, you cannot be relatively dead. The victims of Auschwitz
provide chilling confirmation.
In that sense, human rights can and should never be treated simply as
an abstract concept. It will always be rooted in the very real - not
theoretical - suffering of individual human beings. To borrow a phrase
from American religion scholar Cornel West, human rights are always
"tactile," not merely cerebral.
Raoul Wallenberg understood this and his mission was true humanistic
philosophy in action. When facing the difficult decision to enter into
a dangerous situation or not, he did not hesitate, but dove straight
in. Raw courage, both physical and moral, is Raoul Wallenberg's true
legacy and on this point, he leaves any postmodern parsing firmly in
the dust. We should show the same determination in the face of
overwhelming odds and continue to demand the full facts about his
disappearance and that of others like him, past and present, missing
in Stalin's Russia, Pol Pot's Cambodia or today's Burma and Darfur.
For a rescuer who became a tragic victim, it would be a most
appropriate tribute.
(For further reading about the post-modern debate, see for example
"Wittgenstein's Poker", by David Edmonds and John Eidinow (2001,
Harper Collins)
Susanne Berger
April 30, 2009
(Independent consultant to the Swedish-Russian Working Group on the
fate of Raoul Wallenberg, 1991-2001)